This is yet another look at misgendering, in which I take a rather less robust view than Naomi – referencing her post here – as to when it might be reasonable to misgender a colleague in the workplace. (I am not looking at it outside that context, because the Equality Act does not govern how people relate to one another in the course of interpersonal relationships.)
I will use the same characters from Naomi’s blog: Jen and Liz. But in my version, Jen is not transitioning – rather, having attended an Alpha course, she has become a practising Christian, while Liz is an avowed atheist. In each case, the situation arises after a casual discussion about their respective plans for the weekend. Jen has told her colleagues that she will be baptised. It leads on to a more general discussion about religion in which, having been asked directly what she thinks, Liz makes clear that she views any religious belief as “delusional,” and refers dismissively to “sky fairies,” “science-deniers” and “medieval superstition.” (In a social conversation in which she was expressly asked, she is entitled to answer.)
Scenario 1
In this scenario, Liz does not repeat her views on religion to Jen, and Jen does not say anything more about her faith to Liz. They continue working together, albeit with some awkward silences.
This is clearly acceptable.
Scenario 2
In this scenario, Liz makes a point of repeating her views on religion to Jen whenever they are together. Liz asks Jen whether she also believes in the tooth fairy, and demands to know why she is wearing a polycotton blouse when there is an edict in Leviticus 19 against wearing clothes made from more than one fabric. In the canteen, she highlights news stories about child abuse in the church or religious wars whenever Jen is nearby. When Jen asks her to tone it down, she points out in a way Jen finds belligerent that her lack of belief is just as much a protected characteristic as Jen’s belief, and suggests sarcastically that Jen practise turning the other cheek.
Liz is clearly harassing Jen.
Scenario 3
Knowing that Liz is an atheist, Jen persistently tries to convert Liz despite Liz’s clear lack of interest, offering to pray with her, and giving her Bible study leaflets. After Liz’s picture is in the papers showing her attending a pro-choice march, Jen tries to interest her in materials including a “post abortion course” run by her church and focusing on forgiveness, which Liz finds particularly offensive because, unknown to Jen, Liz had an abortion aged 15 after being date-raped.
Jen is clearly harassing Liz, even if she was unaware of Liz’s personal history.
Scenario 4
In this scenario, Liz does not target Jen in that she does not seek her out to denigrate her views and she does not repeat her own views to Jen directly. However, every time she mentions Jen’s name, she references their opposing views – with sentences such as “I’ll have to ask Jen, whose belief in a deity I do not share, if she can make 20 copies of that” or “Can we check if Paul, Amy, and Jen (whose belief in a deity I do not share) can make the meeting?”
Putting aside for a moment that this scenario is necessarily artificial, would it be harassment? She is not saying it directly to Jen. Her own (lack of) belief is indeed protected. There is no evidence that she is treating Jen badly; she just doesn’t share her beliefs. And yet I think that most people would agree that this is indeed harassment, because in every single interaction Liz has about Jen, if not to Jen, she uses a phrase that reminds her colleagues that Liz thinks that Jen’s religious beliefs are nonsense. Would it make a difference if she had used less forthright language about her own atheism at the outset? I think probably very little, if any.
***
I cannot see any way in which a person could ‘misgender’ a colleague behind their back, even while avoiding using any pronoun but “you / your” to their face, without falling into the same error. Every interaction about the person serves only to reiterate and reinforce the disputed issue, and to remind everyone present of the subject’s biological sex. On that basis I tentatively disagree with Naomi’s view that refusing to use someone’s preferred pronouns will “almost never” amount to harassment.
This of course raises the question as to whether requiring an employee to use preferred pronouns stumbles into the same trap. Using the same, admittedly imperfect, analogy, would it amount to requiring Liz to refer to Jen as “Jen (whose faith I share)” at all times? On balance I don’t think that it would. This is partly because employees do say – may even be required to say – things at work which they would not say outside work – such as “have a nice day” to a customer upon whom they wish nothing but leeches and misery, or “our products are the best” when their own preference is the product of a competitor.
But it is also because, socially, pronouns have a little more fluidity than the GC view tends to admit. ‘Passing’ trans people, however few in number, have been referred to in their preferred pronouns since Lili Elbe in the 1930s, through to Christine Goodwin in the 1990s and on to today. The use of feminine pronouns among effeminate gay men has been both reality and the subject of comedy, sometimes self-deprecating comedy, for decades. Are we really to believe that a neurotypical employee who could understand that “ooh, get her” might refer to a male person would still find referring to John / Jen as “her” impossible? And is it really coherent to say that using a socially feminine-coded name – a proper noun – is a reasonable request for a male person but using a socially feminine-coded pronoun – a substitute for that proper noun – is not?
While it is of little immediate help to employees, HR departments, or those with the protected characteristics of gender reassignment or gender critical belief, the historical tendency of the English language to develop along the path of least difficulty may resolve this over the next century or so. In 2121, the use of the singular “he/she” may be as archaic as the 2021 use of the singular “thou/thee,” retained only in local dialect or historical language, or as completely obsolete as the 1021 use of the dual pronoun (wit – we two, git – you two). Equally plausibly, in 2121, linguistics students may be studying as a sociolinguistic phenomenon the brief historic revival of the Chaucerian singular ‘they’ in the 2010-2030 period. Who knows?
Meanwhile, at least until there is a reasonable body of case law on the subject, I think that ‘misgendering’ a specific colleague may very arguably amount to harassment. Either Naomi or I will be wrong – or, given how case law develops, we will both be right and wrong on different points and at different times.
Take a scenario, I am looking for a driving instructor for my 17yo daughter.
A neighbour recommends “Anna, I highly recommend her, she taught me”.
I this send my daughter off in a car, alone with a TIM, complete with penis and other male traits.
My refusal not to use pronouns is not based in beliefs or preference, it’s a safety issue. And no, it doesn’t matter if it’s in work or out, because it’s normalising us to ignore very real, natural and essential safety reflexes.
I’ve no idea what the law will say about that.. guess that will come with time.
Two thoughts on this:
1) IMO the difference between the comments by Liz in scenario 4 about religious beliefs and the manifestation of GC beliefs in the same scenario is that, unlike the comments about Jen’s religious beliefs (which could easily be omitted from Liz’s references to Jen), Liz has no choice but to declare a view on the issue of sex/gender when speaking about Jen in the third person. Liz either uses Jen’s preferred pronouns (going against her own beliefs), express her own views by using sexed pronouns for Jen or use Jen’s name instead of pronouns (clunky and quite possibly still amounting to harassment if the author of the blog is correct).
2) the assumption that people using sexed pronouns are doing so primarily because they think Jen’s views are nonsense misses a key motivating factor in using sexed pronouns – the motivation being that using gendered pronouns is promoting the arguably misogynystic belief that gender stereotypes define sex and that using ‘gendered’ pronouns is actively damaging for women’s rights. An employer can tell employees to do all sorts of unpleasant things perfectly lawfully but, arguably, asking female employees in particular to reinforce a belief that they sincerely believe is damaging to the interests of women and girls, falls outside the scope of a reasonable management instruction.
I think there’s a material difference in scenario 4 between:
and:
In the first, Liz goes out of her way to add in a superfluous phrase that has nothing to do with the purpose of the sentence and it is clearly deliberate and deliberately intended to have an effect either just of signalling her views on religion to others or to mock Jen’s views.
In the second, it may be seen as ‘misgendering’ by some (but not necessarily by everyone), but the use of a pronoun is necessary to convey the meaning of the sentence (at least in the sense of avoiding having to repeat Jen’s name, which is difficult and linguistically awkward in many cases). But unless Liz admitted it was intentional, how would anyone ever know?
1. With the announcement on 18th Nov 2021 by Nancy Kelley of Stonewall that it is not possible to change sex this means that misgendering should only apply to those with the protected characteristic of gender reassignment.
2. The only applicable pronouns for a TW or TM are xie/xer.
3. To use she/her to a trans woman is a lie as it can only apply to a biological woman.
4. The responsibility of stating a preferred pronoun should be on the TW, noone else. This is the same as entering a restaurant where the obligation is on the customer to state they are vegan or vegetarian. I do not have to announce that I am an omnivore or carnivore
5. Non-binary gender is a nonsense. A person is either male, female or trans on the gender reasignment path.