Discrimination law and the experimental method

I want to apply yesterday’s dazzling insight that peanuts have to be left out of peanut-free meals to the words of the Equality Act and the specific question before the Supreme Court in For Women Scotland v Scottish Ministers, to be heard later this month. This is another fairly short point, though a little more technical than yesterday’s. 

Broadly, the job of the EqA is to prohibit discrimination because of the various protected characteristics. But there are exceptions, so that it remains lawful for director of a play to insist that Juliet is played by a girl and Romeo by a boy, or for a charity to define its beneficiaries by reference to race, national origin or sexual orientation. 

Paragraphs 26 and 27 of schedule 3 make it lawful to provide separate-sex services, and single-sex services, in situations engaging considerations like bodily privacy and dignity. They are expressed in general terms: what’s permitted is providing “single-sex” services or “separate services for persons of each sex”. Obviously that means excluding persons of the other sex. And the exclusion can only be a blanket rule, or the service can’t truthfully be described as separate or single-sex, just as you can’t describe a meal as “peanut free” if you sometimes put peanuts in it. 

That much is straightforward, or ought to be. (There is in fact plenty of dissent to it out there, some of it undeniably heavyweight. Nevertheless, I think the law is clear.)

The question for the Supreme Court in FWS is whether the protected characteristic of sex in the EqA — whether someone is regarded as a man or a woman — is affected by section 9(1) of the GRA, so that a man with a gender recognition certificate declaring him to be a woman counts as a woman for the purposes of discrimination law. In other words, whether “sex” in the EqA just means sex; or whether it means sex except for people with GRCs, in which case it means the sex they are deemed to be because of their GRI. We can call these two possibilities “sex” and “certificated sex” for short. 

The answer to this question determines what kind of discrimination a man with a GRC declaring him to be a woman is subjected to if he is excluded from a women-only service. 

The law has developed a thought experiment, complete with imaginary “experimental control”, as the way of finding out whether someone has suffered discrimination for a particular reason. You don’t have to be a scientist to use experimental controls: we all do it pretty intuitively. 

Suppose your desk lamp isn’t working. Is it the bulb? Is the socket it’s plugged into live? Is it the fuse in the plug? Is the switch in the “on” position? You  find out which is the culprit by trying different things one by one. You change the bulb, keeping everything else the same. Does it light? If so, the problem was the bulb. If not, you put the old bulb back, and try the switch in the other position. Still no light? Switch the switch back, and plug the lamp into a socket you know is live. 

Similarly, if Chris is refused entry to the women’s changing room on account of his obviously male appearance, is that because of his sex? The common sense answer is “yes”. But a GRC transcends (or confounds) common sense: if it operates in the context of the EqA, what matters is Chris’s certificated sex, not his actualy sex, so it tells us that Chris is a woman. To find out whether Chris has been excluded because of his sex, we have to compare him with someone who is of the opposite sex, and ask whether that person would have been excluded, too. 

So, obedient to the pretence required of us by Chris’s GRC, we set to work constructing a comparator. We say “Chris is a woman, so a person of the opposite sex is a man, let’s call him Christopher. This is a women-only space, so Christopher would have been excluded just like Chris. So Chris wasn’t excluded because of his (deemed female) sex, because a person of the opposite sex would also have been excluded.” (In truth, the chances are no-one will ever do anything to Chris because of his “female” sex, because it’s almost certainly obvious that he’s a bloke.)

If we run the same thought experiment on the different PC of gender reassignment, we get a different answer. The law tells us that Chris is a woman (even while our senses tell us different). Chris is a woman with the PC of gender reassignment: although legally a woman, he is a woman not by physiology, but by legal deeming. Obviously a woman without the PC of gender reassignment — that is, an actual female woman — would not have been excluded. So we have our answer: the reason Chris has been excluded is because of his PC of gender reassignment, not his sex. 

That means that excluding Chris can’t be justified under ¶26 or 27 of schedule 3, because those operate to permit sex discrimiation. But it may still be lawful to exclude Chris, because ¶28 of schedule 3 provides that it’s not unlawful to discriminate on grounds of gender reassignment in relation to the provision of single or separate-sex services, provided “the conduct in question is a proportionate means of achieving a legitimate aim”. 

Remember, all this reasoning is proceeding on the assumption that that a GRC changes Chris’s sex for the purposes of the EqA. The weird thing about ¶28, on this assumption, is that it seems to say you have to work out whether the thing you did — excluding Chris — was a proportionate means of achieving a legitimate aim. But it’s always going to be — because, well, peanuts. If the space or service is single-sex, you can’t let a man in (even a man with a certificate), or in every sense that matters it’s no longer a single-sex space. A legal fiction can deem a man married to another man to be in a heterosexual marriage, or deem him to be female for pension purposes, etc, but  it doesn’t actually change the reality or the real consequences of a male body (or even the real consequences of the theoretical possibility of a male body). It won’t affect the trauma reaction of the already-traumatised female user of that space, or the justifiable outrage and affront of the non-traumatised woman who looks up when taking her knickers off to meet the eye of a man in a space she was told was for women only. The fact that the man in question has a secret certificate at home in a drawer won’t — even if somehow she knows about it — make her feel any less embarrassed, angry or alarmed. 

So ¶28 seems to call for  “case by case” decision-making in a situation in which only a blanket rule will do. I explored the practical impossibility of that here: https://www.legalfeminist.org.uk/2022/02/16/admission-to-women-only-spaces-and-case-by-case-assessment/

There are a lot of reasons why the Supreme Court should find for FWS, and this is only a relatively small one. But I think it’s pleasingly neat. 

The reason I say that is that the “certificated sex” assumption leads you into this weird, artificial, counter-factual reasoning about when you can and can’t exclude Chris — and you end up apparently having to make a case-by-case assessment of something that can only be satisfactorily dealt with by way of a general rule, precisely because the “single-sexness” of the space is about what you tell the female users of the space, and whether they can trust you. It’s not really about Chris and his individual characteristics at all. 

But as soon as you remove the GRA spanner from the works of the EqA, this bit of the machine starts running smoothly and rationally. 

On that assumption — that s.9(1) of the GRA doesn’t affect the EqA — this bit of the law can recognise Chris as the man he looks like, and is. He’s excluded because of his sex, which for these purposes remains male. And that’s lawful under ¶26 or 27 if it’s lawful to run a single-sex space at all. 

So what’s ¶28 for, on this hypothesis? Good question! I’m glad you asked it, because the answer is elegant and satisfying. The point of ¶28 is to make it lawful, where appropriate, to exclude not men, but some women from the space, because of their PC of gender reassignment. 

Mostly, women who say they are men (“trans men”) will be perfectly welcome in women-only spaces. That’s because they are women, with female bodies. Their presence won’t affront, humiliate or alarm anyone, and they are likely to have the same needs as any other woman. 

But some “trans men” have taken extreme steps to look like men. Women who do this can often do it quite successfully, for precisely the same reason that men who say they are women almost always remain very visibly male. The reason is testosterone. Testosterone is a powerful drug, and a one-way ticket. A man who has gone through male puberty will almost never be able to disguise its effects successfully in later life. But when a woman takes testosterone, she’s likely to acquire a much more male-looking physique, a broken male-sounding voice, facial hair and male-pattern baldness. So some women with the PC of gender reassignment really do look and sound pretty much like men, and there will be circumstances in which it is genuinely necessary to exclude them from women-only spaces for the sake of the other women in them. 

Obviously, this is a fact-sensitive judgement which will depend on the particular nature of the space or service, who else is likely to be using it, how it is organised, and how convincingly masculine is the appearance of the trans-identifying woman in question. In other words, it calls for precisely the kind of “case by case” decision-making that ¶28 seems to envisage. The difference is that on this hypothesis — that “sex” in the EqA simply means “sex” —“case by case” makes perfect sense.

10 thoughts on “Discrimination law and the experimental method”

    1. No, I’ve written about that before as I think you know. That (among other things) is what I mean by “heavyweight”. But (a) not binding; (b) wrong; (c) inconsistent with the Inner House judgment in FWS.

    1. Yes, it’s inconsistent with the explanatory note. ENs can assist with interpretation, but they are not the law.

      How about writing some serious analysis that explains why SG should win next week? There’s a striking lack of that from your side. If you write something, I’ll link to it.

  1. I first came across this set of controversies in the context of a protest (ish) group called Deep Green Revolution, so I think of it as the Deep Green Revolution question, summarised as: when is a trans-woman a woman, for the purposes of women’s only spaces.

    I tend to make myself unpopular when I express opinions about it, and I seem not to have learned yet, not to do so.

    My first response is to:
    > We can call these two possibilities “sex” and “certificated sex” for short.

    I read this naming as tendentious. It tacitly asserts that sex assigned at birth is the unmarked category. That is close to the core of the assumptions that, as I understand the matter from the outside, trans-people experience as discriminatory. If you had, for example, called them “birth sex” and “certificated sex”, then you would not be supporting the tacit assumption, or not as much.

    My second response is a practical one. Suppose that there is a service which is (for example) health-critical for its recipients. Suppose that it is organised as a separate-sex service. You have mentioned retraumatising birth-sex women in vulnerable circumstances, by confronting them with bodies which are not reliably not male, and I agree that this is a very relevant consideration. Now consider a birth-sex man who is now trans-female, whose transition was surrounded by male-on-male trauma, so sending her to the male separation of the service is not appropriate.

    Supposing that your view of the court case flourishes, what is your view on how such services are appropriately provided to such persons?

    1. It’s one of the great triumphs of gender identity theory that it has made many people read simple truth as tendentious.

      So no, calling sex “sex”, and referring to the legal fiction created by a Gender Recognition Certificate as “certificated sex” is not tendentious, simply accurate. If I could get a government panel to certify me as 6′ tall, my height (actual, literal, truthful or what you will) would still be 5’3½”. If you think the claim that a person can change sex by a process of government certification is in some way less fanciful or unreal than the idea that I could be certified tall, I’ll be interested to understand why.

      No doubt some men are so traumatised by male violence that they will need female counsellors and therapists, and will be unable to make use of therapy groups of which other men are members. Appropriate provision should be made for such men, whether or not they say they are women, but “appropriate” here does not include foisting them on women who need women-only groups. That’s because a women-only group with a man in it isn’t women-only, any more than a peanut-free dish is peanut-free if it’s got a peanut in it.

      It may be difficult to provide group sessions for such men if there is insufficient demand from other men who say they are women, but that still doesn’t mean they should be imposed on vulnerable women. Women are not theatrical props or therapeutic aids to be instrumentalised for the benefit of men.

      1. Firstly, thank you for coming back to me, and for encouraging me to think about my assumptions. That’s much better than average of the times that I have waded into these waters.

        > If you think the claim that a person can change sex by a process of government certification is in some way less fanciful or unreal than the idea that I could be certified tall, I’ll be interested to understand why.

        I’ve come from sociology, where the best account of sex and gender that I’m aware of is “Doing Gender” by Candace West and Don Zimmerman. They observe that, in practice, the sex recorded for a person on a birth certificate is a decision made by a doctor, based on examining the outside of the person’s body close to the time of birth. For a small number of people, different countries would run their processes correctly and make different decisions, so yes, a change in a process of government could change a person’s sex, as it would have been recorded at birth. If there was such a change, whether it applied retroactively, and under what set of conditions, would be a public policy decision.

        I am aware of folk-stories about some US state legislating PI to be 4. I don’t know how much difference it made in practice. I think that if your height was legislated as you describe, many people would ignore it, probably including you continuing to buy clothes that fit. So option-space to legislate differently seems to me to be more real for certificated sex than for height.

        Going back to West and Zimmerman, they are defining ‘sex category’ as styles of self-presentation that are visible from a difference, and ‘gender’ as styles of behaviour in actual circumstances. I gloss their account of normality as behaving so that people would not be surprised by one’s self-presentation, and presenting so people would not be surprised by one’s sex as recorded at birth. In the narrowest interpretation, this is purely a comment about their technical terms.

        I think that there were times in Britain when gender inconsistent with sex category, and sex category inconsistent with birth-certificate sex were punishable, sometimes socially and sometimes with the criminal law. I would not want to go back to that.

        > It’s one of the great triumphs of gender identity theory that it has made many people read simple truth as tendentious.

        I think that the truth in question is only simple often, and not always. I think that campaigning for it to be simple always could be on the path to punishing people who don’t fit the simple story. I do not know whether you are campaigning to resume that punishment. If you were, then it would fit the definition in etymologyonline, which is about reasoning which is led by the purpose that it surves:
        https://www.etymonline.com/word/tendentious

        > Appropriate provision should be made for such men, [to receive care for trauma]

        Looking around the definitional conflict, I agree. I don’t know to what extent it happens in practice. I think that you are tacitly assuming individual care, by people who are informed of a person’s history inside medical privilege. I also don’t know in what circumstances that is available and appropriate. Yes, group processes that were divided into many fine categories would be hard to administer.

        > that still doesn’t mean they should be imposed on vulnerable women

        I agree. Vulnerable people should be protected from harmful surprises, and what counts as a harmful surprise should be consistent with the vulnerable person’s definition. The way Deep Green Revolution explained this, which made them unpopular, was: it’s not your anatomy that I’m afraid of, it’s your socialisation.

        I don’t have any magic plan to square this circle. I just think that claiming that it’s all simple is on one of many paths to doing harm.

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.